1  Propositional Logic

A proposition is a sentence that can be evaluated to true or false.

An indivisible proposition is called an atom, or atomic proposition.

Propositional logic focuses on the composition of logic sentences and truth value of the resulting compounds, called propositional formulas. It does not study the context of logic sentences.

A logic operator (\neg, \land, \lor, \rightarrow) is a symbol used to connect sentences in a way that the value of the compound sentence produced depends only on that of the original sentences and on the meaning of the connective.

\neg has the highest binding priority.

\land and \lor bind more tightly than \rightarrow.

\rightarrow has the lowest binding priority and is right associative:

i.e. p \land \neg q \rightarrow r \rightarrow s \rightarrow t \equiv ((p \land ( \neg q)) \rightarrow (r \rightarrow (s \rightarrow t))

A formula is well-formed if it’s composed using the following inductive construction rules:

The well-formedness can be checked through its parse tree, built up by applying the inductive formula construction rules in reverse. It starts by breaking down the formula through the main operation (the last applied in the formula construction), or equivalently the operator that is to be processed at the last step during the formula evaluation. Then for each subformula, we further break it down through the main operator. We repeat the process until we arrive at only atoms.

A parse tree represents a well-formed formula if:

  1. The root is an atom

  2. The root in \neg and there is only one well-formed subtree

  3. The root is \land, \lor or \rightarrow and there are two well-formed subtrees.

In the parse tree of a well-formed formula, all leaf nodes are atoms.

1.1 Logic equivalencies

Two statements are logically equivalent if they have the same truth value in every combination of truth value assignment to component atoms.

Here some logic equivalencies:

  • Identity laws: p \land T \equiv p p \lor F \equiv p

  • Domination laws: p \lor T \equiv T p \land F \equiv F

  • Idempotent laws:

p \vee p \equiv p

p \wedge p \equiv p

  • Double negation law:

\neg\neg p \equiv p

  • Commutative laws:

p \wedge q \equiv q \wedge p

p \vee q \equiv q \vee p

  • Associative laws:

p \wedge (q \wedge r) \equiv (p \wedge q) \wedge r

p \vee (q \vee r) \equiv (p \vee q) \vee r

  • Distributive laws:

p \wedge (q \vee r) \equiv (p \wedge q) \vee (p \wedge r)

p \vee (q \wedge r) \equiv (p \vee q) \wedge (p \vee r)

  • De Morgan’s laws:

\neg(p \wedge q) \equiv \neg p \vee \neg q

\neg(p \vee q) \equiv \neg p \wedge \neg q

  • Absorption laws:

p \wedge (p \vee q) \equiv p

p \vee (p \wedge q) \equiv p

  • Contrapositive of implication: p \rightarrow q \equiv \neg q \rightarrow \neg p

  • Negation of implication: \neg(p \rightarrow q) \equiv p \wedge \neg q

1.2 Logic Arguments

A logic argument is a sequence of propositions. The last proposition is called conclusion, while all the other are premises.

An argument is valid if when all the premises are true, the conclusion is also true. So an argument is valid based only on its logic form, therefore a valid argument could have a false conclusion, and an invalid argument could have a true conclusion.

An argument is sound if it is valid and all of its premises are true.

1.3 Inference rules

A valid argument can be proved by applying some inference rules and logic equivalences, presented here in the following format:

\dfrac{\text{premise 1, premise 2, ..., premise m}}{\text{conclusion}} <\text{name of the rule}>

  • Or-introduction (\lori): \dfrac{\varphi}{\varphi \lor \psi} \lor i

  • And-elimination (\lande): \dfrac{\varphi \land \psi}{\varphi} \land e \; \; \; \; \; \; \dfrac{\varphi \land \psi}{\psi} \land e

  • And-introduction (\landi): \dfrac{\varphi, \psi}{\varphi \land \psi} \land i

  • Modus Ponens: \dfrac{\varphi \rightarrow \psi, \varphi}{\psi} MP

  • Modus Tollens: \dfrac{\varphi \rightarrow \psi, \neg \psi}{\neg \varphi} MT

  • Implication-introduction (\rightarrow i): \dfrac{\boxed{\begin{array}{c}\varphi \\ \vdots \\ \psi \end{array}}}{\varphi \rightarrow \psi} \rightarrow i The box is called an assumption box. We need to open it when we make an assumption on a statement. When it is closed, we get an implication from the assumed statement of the last statement in the box.

  • Or-elimination (\lor e): \dfrac{\varphi \lor \psi, \neg \varphi}{\psi} \lor e \dfrac{\varphi \lor \psi, \neg \psi}{\varphi} \lor e \dfrac{\varphi \lor \psi, \varphi \rightarrow \lambda, \psi \rightarrow \lambda}{\lambda} \lor e

  • Proof by Contradiction: it starts by assuming that the opposite proposition is true, and then show that the assumption made leads to a contradiction. We use \perp to represent the contradiction: \dfrac{\boxed{\begin{array}{c}\neg \varphi \\ \vdots \\ \perp \end{array}}}{\varphi} PBC

  • Law of excluded middle: it can be used as a premise; as using the or-elimination rule, we open an assumption box for the proposition and another one for its negation: \vdash \varphi \lor \neg \varphi

1.4 Satisfiability

A formula is satisfiable if there is a truth values assignment in which the formula evaluates to true.

A formula is valid if for every truth value assignment it evaluates to true.